PROJECTIVE INCIDENCE STRUCTURES

Introduction edit

The object of this article is to describe the axiomatic foundations of the theory of projective incidence structures.

The main, and historically first, application is in the foundations of projective and affine geometry. However, the theory of such structures has applications in communication theory and in cryptography.

The aim is to develope the classification of projective incidence structures up to the point where one is lead to the study of specific algebraic structures such as : GL_n (R), where specific R is a division ring or specific ternary rings.

The first classifying facto is the dimension of the structure.

  • Structures of dimension greater than 2
  • Structures of dimension 2

For structures of dimension 2 the classifications is by the Desargues axiom

  • Desarguesian planes
  • Non-desarguesian planes

A projective incidence structure can be associated with an algebraic coordinate structure and the "isotopic" equivalence classes of these algebraic structures classify all the projective incidence structures.


Geometry :

Combinatorics

What we will describe edit

  • If N > 2, then any projective incidence structure of dimension N is isomorphic to GLN(R), where R is a division ring. It is isomorphic to GLN(F), where F is a field (finite or infinite) if and only if the Pappus theorem is true.
  • If N = 2, then a projective incidence structure is isomorphic to GL2(R), R a division ring, if and only Desargues' theorem holds.
  • If N = 2 and Desargues' theorem does not hold, then there is a rich family of Non-Desarguesian planes.


Vocabulary edit

The unique line k containg the distinct points A and B is called the line joining A and B. It will be noted as AB.

The unique point P contained in two distinct lines l and k will be called the intersection of l and k.

The axioms edit

A projective incidence structure is a set of objects called "points" , denoted by   and a set of distinguished sub-sets of   called "lines", denoted by   which satisfy a certain number of simple axioms. We denote points by upper-case latin letters, lines by lower-case latin letters, and later, planes (to be defined later) by upper-case greek letters.

The pair   satisfying the following axioms is called a projective incidence structure.

A1. If  , then there is at least one   such that  .
A2. If  , then there is at most one   such that  .
A3. There are at least three points on any line.
A4. There is at least one point   and at least one line   such that  
A5. If   are not all on the same line and   are such that   is on the line   and   on the line  , then the lines   and   have a point in common.
Axiom 5 can be thought of as saying : If ABC is a triangle and a line intersects two sides of the triangle, then it intersects the third side.'

In the mathematical litterature there are many variations for the set of axioms to be used to define a projective incidence structure. However, they are all equivalent and given two sets of axioms it is a simple exercice to deduce one set from the other.

The following theorems, some of which are used as axioms in other expositions, are simple consequences of the above axioms.

  • Theorem 1 - Two distinct points are on one, and only one, line.
  • Theorem 2 - There are at least two distinct lines.
  • Theorem 3 - If   are distinct points on the line  , then   are distinct points on the line  .
  • Theorem 4 - Two distinct lines cannot have more than one common point.
  • Theorem 5 - There exists four points   no three of which are collinear.

The following theorem is slightly less evident.

  • Theorem 6 - All   have the same cardinality.
Corollary - If the set   is finite, then all lines in   have the same number of points.
Proof
If  , we show that there exists a bijective map   from the set of points on   to the set of ponts on  . We can suppose that  .
Case 1 : The lines   intersect at a point  .
Let  . By axiom A3 there is a point   on the line  .
If  , then the line   intersects   in a unique point  . That is, the map   defined by :   and   is an injection from   into  . Similarly we can construct an injection  . By the Schröder-Bernstein theorem there exists a bijection between the sets  .
Case 2 : The lines   do not intersect. Let   and   the line  . By case 1 the bijections   exist, and so the composite map   is a bijection between  .

Dimension of an incidence structure edit

Definition : If   are three points not all on the same line and   is the line joining   and  , the class of all points on the lines joining   to the points on the line  l is called the plane determined by   and  . Small greek letters will be used to denote planes.

Theorem - Any two lines on the same plane   have a common point.

Theorem - The plane   determined by a line   and a point   is identical with the plane   determined by a line   and a point  , provided   and   are on  .

Corollary - There is one and only one plane determined by three non-collinear points, or by a line and one point not on the line or by two intersecting lines.

Theorem - Two distinct points planes which have two distinct points   in common contain all the points on the line   and have no other points in common.

Corollary - Two distinct planes cannot have more than one common line.

Points have dimension 0

Lines have dimension 1

Planes have dimension 2

If   is an incidence structure of dimension   and  . The set of all points on the lines joining   to the points of   is an n-dimensional structure  

The analogous theorems to the above are straightforward.

Definition : If all the points of   are in  , the the incidence structure has dimension  .


Thus the dimension of an incidence structure is either a positive integer or infinity.

Infinite dimensional incidence structures exist.

The collineation group and some sub-groups edit

Depuis Félix Klein and his Erlanger programme, it is always a fruitful occupation in mathematics when studying a mathematical structure to examine in detail those properties which are conserved by symmetries, i.e. subgroups of the automorphism group.

In the case of projective incidence structures the exercise yields some beautiful mathematics and is still an active source of research.

An intuitive motivation for some of the formel definitions edit

Imagine two planes   in Euclidean three-space, which intersect in a line   and two points   not on either plane.

We project the point   onto the point   by drawing the line   and   is the point of intersection with the plane  . This procedure gives an isomorphisme between the points of   and   and lines in   are mapped into lines on  . Call this isomorphism  .

We can define a similar isomorphism,  , from  .

The combined map   is an automorphism of  . This automorphism has several interesting features :

  1. Every point on the line   is mapped onto itself. The line is fixed by the automorphism.
  2. The point of intersection,   of the line   with the plane   is also a fixed point.
  3. Any line in the plane   which passes through   is mapped into itself (the points are not fixed).

Automorphisms with these properties, which arise from a simple and intuitive geometrical construction, will play a very important role in the study of projective incidence structures.

Definitions edit

  • A collineation is an automorphism   of   which also maps   onto itself in the sense that if  , then the image of the set  , that is   is also  .

The set of collineations form a group under composition,  .

Note : The identity is a collineation and there there exist incidence structures for which it is the ONLY collineation.


Lemma - If   is a collineation of  , then for two distinct points   the image of the line   is the line  .


  • If   and for   then   is a fixed point of  .

A collineation maps   onto   and there are two possibilities for the notion of fixed line :

  • If   and   as sets, then we say   preserves the line  .
  • If   and  , then we say that   fixes the line  .

If   is a hyperplane of dimension  , then we can define the collineations   which preserve or which fix   in the obvious way.

Simple consequences of the definitions edit

Theorem If  , then :(i)   has at least one fixed point. (ii)   preserves at least one line.

Proof - Since any   contains at least one plane, it suffices to prove the case for planes.
(i) Suppose that there is a line   that is not preserved by  , then  , hence   is a fixed point of  .
Now suppose that all lines are preserved by  . Then   which implies that   is a fixed point.
(ii) Suppose that no line is preserved by  . Let   be distinct lines, hence  . The points   are fixed by  .
If  , the the line   is preserved by  . This is contrary to the hypotheses, hence   and so all the lines in the plane must pass through  .
Let   and different from  .
The line   must pass through  . The lines   have   in common. If they are distinct they cannot have   in common, so they are not distinct, and this implies that  , a contradiction, since we are assuming that no lines are preserved.
Hence   preserves at least one line.


Theorem The set of   which preserve a line   form a sub-group  .


Theorem The set of   which fix a line   form a sub-group  .


The groups   are important ; they will give rise to affine geometry, the carcterisation of n-dimensional projective structures. We state and prove some simple theorems which will enable us to better understant the collineations which fix a given line.


Clarify the details of  :

  • Given any two lines of P there is a collineation that maps L1 to L2
  • Given any line in P, then there is a collineation, different from the identity, which preserves the line.
This shows that the collineation group is not trivial and is 'large'.



Theorem - If  , then  , the identity collineation. i.e. A collineation different from the identity cannot fix more than one line.

Proof
Case 1 : The two lines have a point in common.
Proof.
Let   be the intersection of the lines   fixed by  .
Let   be a point of the plane not on these lines.
Let   be two points on   distinct from  .
Suppose that the line   intersects   in   and that the line   intersects   in  .
The points  , are fixed by  , so the lines   and   are preserved by  . Hence their intersection   is fixed by  . But   is any point in the plane not on   or on  . Thus all the points of the plane are fixed by  . Hence,   is the identity collineation.
Case 2 : The two lines have no point in common.
Proof.


Theorem - If  , then there is at most one point  .

Proof
Lemma 2 : A collineation of a plane   which fixes a line   and two points   not on   is the identity collineation
Proof Let   be a point in the plane not on the line   and not on the line  .
Let   intersect   at   and   at  .
The lines   and   are distinct and   is their unique point of intersection.
The points   are fixed by the collineation, hence the line   is preserved by the collineation, likewise the line   is preserved by the collineation.
This implies that the intersection of these two lines is fixed by the collineation. But   is any point not on   and not on the line  . This implies that the line   is fixed by the collineation, and by lemma 1, the collineation must be the identity.

The next theorem proves that if a collineation has a fixed line, then it must have a unique fixed point with the property that all lines through the fixed point are preserved by the collineation.

Theorem - If  , then   and any line   through   is preserved by  . The point   is unique.

N.B.   may or may not be on the line  .
Proof
By lemma 2 there is at most one point not on the fixed line which has the stated properties.

We now show that there cannot exist a point on the line L with these properties. Suppose that such a point, C1 exists. If Q is a point not on L and different from C, then the line C2.Q is preserved by alpha. The line CQ is preserved by alpha. The intersection of these two lines is then a fixed point of alpha, nameley Q, and Q is different from C. Thus alpha has twou fixed points not on L, hence alpha is the identity by lemma 2.

Similarly there cannot be two distinct fixed points C1, C2 on L which preseve all lines throug C1 and C2.
Thus, the point C, if it exists is unique. We now show that such a point does, in fact, exist.
Suppose that alpha has a fixed point C, C not on L. Any line m through C intersects L at a point Q. The points P and Q are fixed by alpha, hence the line m is preserved by alpha. Thus, any line through C is preserved by alpha.
Now suppose that alpha does not fix any point not on the line L.
Let P be any point, then   and  .
The line   intersects   in a point  .
The line m = P.C. and so alpha (m) = alpha (P).alpha (C) = PC. Thus m is preserved by alpha.
Let Q be a point not on L or m, then Q is on a preserved line n. The intersection of m and n must be a fixed point and by hypothesis there are no fixed points not on L. Hence the point of intersection must be the point C. Thus every line preserved by alpha must pass through C and every line through C is preserved.

The 'dual' theorem is also true.

Theorem - If   and there exists a   and all lines through   are preserved by  , then there exists a line   that is fixed by  . The line   is unique.


Lemma Let   be a collineation of   and   a hyperplane such that each point is fixed by  . Then :

(i) There exists a point   such that each line through   is preserved by  .
(ii) If  , then   is unique.
Proof - If  , the   is a centre : for each line through   is preserved (if   is on C, then  . The line   is preserved.
Suppose now that no point outside   is fixed.
Let  . Let  , then the lines :   and   i.e. the line   is preserved.
We now show that any line through   is preserved.
Let  . The line   passes through  . For let  , then  
Hence the points   are contained in a common plane  .
Therefore the lines   intersect at  .
Since the lines   are preserved by   satisfies  .
Thedrefore  , thus it must coincide with  .
Hence all the lines of the form   pass through the point  . Thus each line trough   is preserved.


Lemma Let   be a collineation of   and   a point such that each line through   is preserved by  . Then :

(i) There exists a hyperplane   which is fixed by  
(ii) The hyperplane is unique.
Proof
Suppose that the line   does not pass by   but is preserved by  . If  , the the line   is preserved by definition. Hence the point of intersection of   and   is a fixed point. But   is any point of   , hence   is a fixed line.


Suppose now the \mathcal{l_{1}} , \mathcal{l_{2}} are two lines which are NOT preserved by \alpha , we will construct a line tha IS preserved by \alpha .
Let  . The points   are fixed by  , hence   is preserved by  .
Since there at least three lines in   there is at least one preserved line that does not pass by   and so is fixed.
We now have to build up a fixed hyperplane.


The above theorems were proved on the assumption that a colleation with a fixed line exists. We investigate the conditions of their existance in the next section.

Central collineations edit

Definition : An   with the above properties is called a Central collineation ;   is the centre and   the axis of the collineation.


Definition : A collineation   of   is a central collineation if there exists a hyperplane   (the axis if   and a oint  , the centre of   such that :

- For every point   i.e. is a fixed point.
- For every line  through     i.e. the line is preserved.

Lemma - Let   be a hyperplane and   a point of  . The set of central collineations with axis   and centre   form a group,   with respect to composition.

N.B. The group is not empty since it contains the identity collineation.

Lemma - Let   and suppose that  . Then   is uniquely determined. In particular the image of any   satisfies :  , where  

Proof The image   of   is subject to the following restrictions :

-The line   is mapped onto itself, so   is on the line  .
- Consider the point   is on the axis of \alpha , so is fixed. X is on the line FP.

Since   is not on   is not on   , thus   is on the intersection of two distinct lines and so uniquely determined. It follows that   is on the image of the line  . The image of  .

Thus   is the intersection of the lines   , hence uniquely determined.

We now show that any   on the line   is also uniquely determined. Replace the pair of points   by any other pair of points   with  , the repeat the above construction to determine   (need to quote axioms to say there exists a point   not fixed and not on  , then use the construction to determine  .

Corollary (Uniqueness of central collineations) - If   :

(a) If  , the P is not fixed by  ;
(b)   is uniquely determined by one pair of points  .

Proof (a) Supose that Q is fixed by \alpha , then we will show that any P \in \mathcal{P} is fixed i.e. \alpha is the identity collineation.

Let X \notin CP , then \alpha (X) = CX \cap FP' = CX \cap FP = X, since X is on FP, so every point not on CP is fixed. We pick a pont X_{0} not on CP and repeat the argument to show that all points of CP are fixed. hence \alpha = \iota.

(b) follows directly from the lemma.


Note : We will be considering the group of central collineations with centre on   (the elations or translations). To show that two elations with the same centre are the same, it suffices to show that for just one point  , that  .




QUESTION : Is it always true that : A collination is the product of a fine number of central collineations.


Theorem - There is at most one central collineation   with given centre  , axis   and pair of points  .

Proof
Lemma - A central collineation   of a plane is completely determined by its axis  , centre   and a pair of points  .
Proof
Let   be any point in the plane. We will show how to determine  .
The line   intersects   at  , a fixed point. The line   intersects the line   at  .
We claim that  , because   must be on the line  , since   preserves all lines through   ;   must also lie on the line   and   is the unique intersection of these lines.

Question : What if L, C, P, Q are not in the plane C, L ?



Theorem If N > 2 there exists a central collineation with any given centre, axis and (P, image(P) ).

Theorem Desargues theorem is true if and only if all the possible central collineations exist.

Cor For N > 2 Desargues theorem is true. For N = 2 we have to introduce as an axion that all possible central collineations exist.

N.B. Check out the little an big Desargues theorems to get the logical structure clear.

If   is non-Desarguenian, the there exist at least one line which is not fixed by any collineation of  .


Definition :

Central collineations with centre on the axis are called elations.
A central collineation with centre NOT on the axis is called a homology/

N.B. In many papers Central collineations are called perspectivities.


Theorem - The homologies with centre C and axis L form an abelian group.


If   are homologies with cetres   and axes  , then   is a collineation with centre   and preserves the line  . The line is not necessarily fixed.


Theorem - The elations with axis   and centre   form a group  

Theorem - The elations with axis   form a group  , the   are subgroups.

Theorem - If   has at least two non-trivial subgroups   and  , then   is an abelian group. The orders of the elements of   is either infinity or all are of finite order  , a fixed prime number.

There exists examples where the group   does not have two such sub-groups.

Question : What are the examples ?

Definition : The group generated by all the elations of   is often called the little projective group.

Question : Is this for different line or for one fixed line ?


Desarguesian and non-desarguesian projective incidence structures edit

The first major classification of projective incidence structures is a binary distinction :

- A desarguesian structure.
- A non-desarguesian structure.

A desarguesian projective structure satisfies an additional axiom, which we give in two forms (Our first theorem will be to show that the two forms of the axiom are equivalent.)

- Axiom 5a : - Axiom 5b :

Theorem - The two forms of axiom 5 are equivalent.

There exist projective incidence structures which satisfy axiom 5 and structures which do not satisfy axiom 5, so the concept of desarguesian structres is a useful one.

Example 1 : (A desarguesian plane)

Example 2 : (Moulton plane)

Example 3 : (Finite not-desarguesian plane)


Theorem A projective incidence structure of dimension N > 2 is desarguesian.

We will see in the section : Algebraic structures associated with projective incidence structures that a desarguesian projection structure of dimension n is isomorphic GLn(R), where R is a division ring.

For two dimensionnel projective incidence structures a great deal of research has centered on finding criteria (usually in termes of the collineation group) which ensure that the plane is desarguesian.

THE BARSOTTI CLASSIFICATION


Artin's axioms 4a, 4b 4b P Get the inter-relations clear !

Axiom 4a Given any two points p, q there is a translation that sends p to q.

Axiom 4b If tau1, tau2 are dfferent non-identity translations with the same traces, then there is a homomorphism that sends tau1 to tau2

Axiom 4b P - For a given P, then given Q, R such that P, Q, R are distict and PQR are collinear, then there is a dilatation which has P as fixed point and sends Q to R

Are thes axioms equivalent ?

Is axiom 4b P equivalent to Desargues theorem ,

Give the Moulton plane example of a non-Desarguesian plane (Refractive index)

QUESTIONS TO CLARIFY

  1. If N >2 are all collineations central , all collineations of a Desarguesian plane ?
  2. Does there exist at least one line that is fixed by by some alpha ?
  3. If alpha has a fixed point does it have a preserved line ?
  4. If alpha has a centre does it have a fixed line ?


Definitions

  1. A collineation of order 2 is an involution
  1. A affine plane is a projective plane with a distinguished lin  
  1. An elation of an affine plane with axis   is translation.
  1. The group generated by all the translations of a plane is the Translation group.
  2. It the translation group of an affine plane is transitive, then the plane is a 'Translation plane.
  1. A projective plane is   transitive with fixed point   and fixed line   if for any pair of points   with  , there exists a   perspectivity  .

Ternary algebraic structures edit

If   is a sub-group of   and   the semi-group of homomorphisms of   we define two binary operations " " and  " as follows :

If   then   defined by  
If   then   defined by  , where " " is the group operation in  

The binary operations   are a priori not assumed to be communtative, associative or distributative.


However, there always exists

  • A two sided 'multiplicative identity' denoted by  such that   and defined   by  .
If   then   such that   and   i.e. every element has a right inverse and a left inverse.
Thus, " " defines a loop.
  • An 'additive zero', denoted by   and defined   by  , the identity element of  , such that    
Il est à noter que  .
An 'additive inverse' : the homomorphism   and defined by   is such that  .
It is suggestive to denote   by   and write :  .
  is associative :  
However,   is commutative if and only if the group   is abelian.

By restricting attention to special groups   this ternary algebraic structure acquires more structure and can become a division ring or even a field. It will be used later to introduce coordinates into projective incidence structures and to characterise them.

Bibliography edit

Books

  • Artin, Emil (1957). Geometric Algebra. New York: Interscience Publishers Inc. pp. 1–103.
  • Beutelspacher, Albrecht; Rosenbaum, Ute (1998). Projective Geometry: From Foundations to Applications (PDF). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 1–103. ISBN 0 521 48364 6.
  • Hall Jr., Marshall (1959). The Theory of Groups. New York: The Macmillan Company. pp. 346–420.


Papers


References edit

Mathematiciens who contributed edit

Notes for WJE edit

Let   be a projective plane and   an involutory collineation, then either   is a perspectivity or   leaves fixed pointwise a proper subplane  .
  • Wagner, A. (1958). "On Projective Planes Transitive on Quadrangles". J. Lond. Math. Soc. 33: 25–33.
Fundamental result : In a desaguesian plane there is a collineation that maps any quadrangle to any other quadrangle. The same is true for alternative planes. He examines the converse problem : what configurations existe in projective structures whose collineation group is transitive on quadrangles ? He proves that if the plane is finite, then it is desarguesian and conjectures that if it is infnite the plane is alternative.


Finite planes

  • Ostrom, T.G. (1956). "Double transivity in finite projective planes". Canad. J. Maths. 8 (2): 563–567.
Let   be a projective plane,   two involutory homologies with centres   and axes  . If   then   is an involutory homology with centre   and axis  .
  • Ostrom, T.G.; Wagner, A (1959). "On projective and affine planes with transitive collineation groups". Math. Zeit. 71: 188–199.
THEOREM A. Let P be a finite projective plane admitting a collineation group doubly transitive on the points of P. Then, P is desarguesian.
THEOREM B. Let P be a finite affine plane admitting a collineation group doubly transitive on the a]fine, then P is a translation plane.
  • Ostrom, T.G. (1970). "A Class of Translation Planes Admitting Elations which are not Translations". Arch. Math. 21: 214-.
  • Piper, F.C. (1963). "Elations of finite projective planes". Math. Zeitschr. 82: 247–258.
  • Coulter, R.S. (2019). "On coordinatising planes of prime power order using finite fields". J. of th Australien Math. Soc. 106 (2): 184–199. arXiv:1609.01337v1.

Algebraic structure

  • Martin, G.E. (1967). "Projective Planes and Isotopic Ternary Rings". American Math. Monthly. 74 (10): 1185–1195. JSTOR 2315659.
  • Kramer, Linus (1994). "The Topology of smooth projective planes". Arch. Math. 63: 85–91.

Infinite dimension structures


When does a planar ternary ring uniquely coordinitise a projective plane?

https://mathoverflow.net/questions/106888/when-does-a-planar-ternary-ring-uniquely-coordinitise-a-projective-plane/160978


projective plane over algebraic structure

https://math.stackexchange.com/questions/734288/projective-plane-over-algebraic-structure

  • A. Wagner , Perspectivities and the little projective group, Algebraic and Topological Foundations of Geometryt, Proc. of a Coll., Utrecht, august 1959, 1962, pages 199-208.
The little projective group = Elation group, often a simple group.
  • T.G. Room, P.B. Kirkpatrick, "Miniquaternion geometry" , Cambridge Univ. Press (1971)
  • W.M. Kantor, "Primitive permutation groups of odd degree, and an application to finite projective planes" J. Algebra , 106 (1987) pp. 15–45
  • G. Pickert, "Projective Ebenen" , Springer (1975)
  • D.R. Hughes, F.C. Piper, "Projective planes" , Springer (1973)
  • H. Lüneburg, "Translation planes" , Springer (1979)
  • K.G.C. von Staudt, "Beiträge zur Geometrie der Lage" , I , Korn , Nürnberg (1865)
  • G. Fano, "Sui postulati fondamentali della geometria proiettiva" Giornale di Mat. , 30 (1892) pp. 106–132
  • I. Singer, "A theorem in finite projective geometry and some applications to number theory" Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. , 43 (1938) pp. 377–385