User:Gro-Tsen/An ordinal collapsing function

This page was used as the draft basis of the article on ordinal collapsing functions and has now been moved there (so read that instead).

This is an attempt to define and explicit a not-too-complicated ordinal collapsing function which should be useful for pedagogical purposes (to construct large countable ordinals).

Definition edit

Let   stand for the first uncountable ordinal  , or, in fact, any ordinal which is (an  -number and) guaranteed to be greater than all the countable ordinals which will be constructed (for example, the Church-Kleene ordinal is adequate for our purposes; but we will work with   because it allows the convenient use of the word countable in the definitions).

We define a function   (which will be non-decreasing and continuous), taking an arbitrary ordinal   to a countable ordinal  , recursively on  , as follows:

Assume   has been defined for all  , and we wish to define  .
Let   be the set of ordinals generated starting from  ,  ,   and   by recursively applying the following functions: ordinal addition, multiplication and exponentiation and the function  , i.e., the restriction of   to ordinals  . (Formally, we define   and inductively   for all natural numbers   and we let   be the union of the   for all  .)
Then   is defined as the smallest ordinal not belonging to  .

In a more concise (although more obscure) way:

  is the smallest ordinal which cannot be expressed from  ,  ,   and   using sums, products, exponentials, and the   function itself (to previously constructed ordinals less than  ).

Here is an attempt to explain the motivation for the definition of   in intuitive terms: since the usual operations of addition, multiplication and exponentiation are not sufficient to designate ordinals very far, we attempt to systematically create new names for ordinals by taking the first one which does not have a name yet, and whenever we run out of names, rather than invent them in an ad hoc fashion or using diagonal schemes, we seek them in the ordinals far beyond the ones we are constructing (beyond  , that is); so we give names to uncountable ordinals and, since in the end the list of names is necessarily countable,   will “collapse” them to countable ordinals.

Computation of values of edit

Predicative start edit

First consider  . It contains ordinals  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,   and so on. It also contains such ordinals as  ,  ,  ,  . The first ordinal which it does not contain is   (which is the limit of  ,  ,   and so on — less than   by assumption). The upper bound of the ordinals it contains is   (the limit of  ,  ,   and so on), but that is not so important. This shows that  .

Similarly,   contains the ordinals which can be formed from  ,  ,  ,   and this time also  , using addition, multiplication and exponentiation. This contains all the ordinals up to   but not the latter, so  . In this manner, we prove that   inductively on  : the proof works, however, only as long as  . We therefore have:

  for all  , where   is the smallest fixed point of  .

(Here, the   functions are the Veblen functions defined starting with  .)

Now   but   is no larger, since   cannot be constructed using finite applications of   and thus never belongs to a   set for  , and the function   remains “stuck” at   for some time:

  for all  .

First impredicative values edit

Again,  . However, when we come to computing  , something has changed: since   was (“artificially”) added to all the  , we are permitted to take the value   in the process. So   contains all ordinals which can be built from  ,  ,  ,  , the   function up to   and this time also   itself, using addition, multiplication and exponentiation. The smallest ordinal not in   is   (the smallest  -number after  ).

We say that the definition   and the next values of the function   such as   are impredicative because they use ordinals (here,  ) greater than the ones which are being defined (here,  ).

Values of   up to the Feferman-Schütte ordinal edit

The fact that   remains true for all   (note, in particular, that  : but since now the ordinal   has been constructed there is nothing to prevent from going beyond this). However, at   (the first fixed point of   beyond  ), the construction stops again, because   cannot be constructed from smaller ordinals and   by finitely applying the   function. So we have  .

The same reasoning shows that   for all  , where   enumerates the fixed points of   and   is the first fixed point of  . We then have  .

Again, we can see that   for some time: this remains true until the first fixed point   of  , which is the Feferman-Schütte ordinal. Thus,   is the Feferman-Schütte ordinal.

Beyond the Feferman-Schütte ordinal edit

We have   for all   where   is the next fixed point of  . So, if   enumerates the fixed points in question. (which can also be noted   using the many-valued Veblen functions) we have  , until the first fixed point of the   itself, which will be  . In this manner:

  •   is the Ackermann ordinal (the range of the notation   defined predicatively),
  •   is the “small” Veblen ordinal (the range of the notations   predicatively using finitely many variables),
  •   is the “large” Veblen ordinal (the range of the notations   predicatively using transfinitely-but-predicatively-many variables),
  • the limit   of  ,  ,  , etc., is the Bachmann-Howard ordinal: after this our function   is constant, and we can go no further with the definition we have given.

Ordinal notations up to the Bachmann-Howard ordinal edit

We now explain how the   function defines notations for ordinals up to the Bachmann-Howard ordinal.

A note about base representations edit

Recall that if   is an ordinal which is a power of   (for example   itself, or  , or  ), any ordinal   can be uniquely expressed in the form  , where   is a natural number,   are non-zero ordinals less than  , and   are ordinal numbers (we allow  ). This “base   representation” is an obvious generalization of the Cantor normal form (which is the case  ). Of course, it may quite well be that the expression is uninteresting, i.e.,  , but in any other case the   must all be less than  ; it may also be the case that the expression is trivial (i.e.,  , in which case   and  ).

If   is an ordinal less than  , then its base   representation has coefficients   (by definition) and exponents   (because of the assumption  ): hence one can rewrite these exponents in base   and repeat the operation until the process terminates (any decreasing sequence of ordinals is finite). We call the resulting expression the iterated base   representation of   and the various coefficients involved (including as exponents) the pieces of the representation (they are all  ), or, for short, the  -pieces of  .

Some properties of   edit

  • The function   is non-decreasing and continuous (this is more or less obvious from is definition).
  • If   with   then necessarily  . Indeed, no ordinal   with   can belong to   (otherwise its image by  , which is   would belong to   — impossible); so   is closed by everything under which   is the closure, so they are equal.
  • Any value   taken by   is an  -number (i.e., a fixed point of  ). Indeed, if it were not, then by writing it in Cantor normal form, it could be expressed using sums, products and exponentiation from elements less than it, hence in  , so it would be in  , a contradiction.
  • Lemma: Assume   is an  -number and   an ordinal such that   for all  : then the  -pieces (defined above) of any element of   are less than  . Indeed, let   be the set of ordinals all of whose  -pieces are less than  . Then   is closed under addition, multiplication and exponentiation (because   is an  -number, so ordinals less than it are closed under addition, multiplication and exponentition). And   also contains every   for   by assumption, and it contains  ,  ,  ,  . So  , which was to be shown.
  • Under the hypothesis of the previous lemma,   (indeed, the lemma shows that  ).
  • Any  -number less than some element in the range of   is itself in the range of   (that is,   omits no  -number). Indeed: if   is an  -number not greater than the range of  , let   be the least upper bound of the   such that  : then by the above we have  , but   would contradict the fact that   is the least upper bound — so  .
  • Whenever  , the set   consists exactly of those ordinals   (less than  ) all of whose  -pieces are less than  . Indeed, we know that all ordinals less than  , hence all ordinals (less than  ) whose  -pieces are less than  , are in  . Conversely, if we assume   for all   (in other words if   is the least possible with  ), the lemma gives the desired property. On the other hand, if   for some  , then we have already remarked   and we can replace   by the least possible with  .

The ordinal notation edit

Using the facts above, we can define a (canonical) ordinal notation for every   less than the Bachmann-Howard ordinal. We do this by induction on  .

If   is less than  , we use the iterated Cantor normal form of  . Otherwise, there exists a largest  -number   less or equal to   (this is because the set of  -numbers is closed): if   then by induction we have defined a notation for   and the base   representation of   gives one for  , so we are finished.

It remains to deal with the case where   is an  -number: we have argued that, in this case, we can write   for some (possibly uncountable) ordinal  : let   be the greatest possible such ordinal (which exists since   is continuous). We use the iterated base   representation of  : it remains to show that every piece of this representation is less than   (so we have already defined a notation for it). If this is not the case then, by the properties we have shown,   does not contain  ; but then   (they are closed under the same operations, since the value of   at   can never be taken), so  , contradicting the maximality of  .

Note: Actually, we have defined canonical notations not just for ordinals below the Bachmann-Howard ordinal but also for certain uncountable ordinals, namely those whose  -pieces are less than the Bachmann-Howard ordinal (viz.: write them in iterated base   representation and use the canonical representation for every piece). This canonical notation is used for arguments of the   function (which may be uncountable).

Examples edit

For ordinals less than  , the canonical ordinal notation defined coincides with the iterated Cantor normal form (by definition).

For ordinals less than  , the notation coincides with iterated base   notation (the pieces being themselves written in iterated Cantor normal form): e.g.,   will be written  , or, more accurately,  . For ordinals less than  , we similarly write in iterated base   and then write the pieces in iterated base   (and write the pieces of that in iterated Cantor normal form): so   is written  , or, more accurately,  . Thus, up to  , we always use the largest possible  -number base which gives a non-trivial representation.

Beyond this, we may need to express ordinals beyond  : this is always done in iterated  -base, and the pieces themselves need to be expressed using the largest possible  -number base which gives a non-trivial representation.

Note that while   is equal to the Bachmann-Howard ordinal, this is not a “canonical notation” in the sense we have defined (canonical notations are defined only for ordinals less than the Bachmann-Howard ordinal).

Conditions for canonicalness edit

The notations thus defined have the property that whenever they nest   functions, the arguments of the “inner”   function are always less than those of the “outer” one (this is a conseequence of the fact that the  -pieces of  , where   is the largest possible such that   for some  -number  , are all less than  , as we have shown above). For example,   does not occur as a notation: it is a well-defined expression (and it is equal to   since   is constant between   and  ), but it is not a notation produced by the inductive algorithm we have outlined.

Canonicalness can be checked recursively: an expression is canonical if and only if it is either the iterated Cantor normal form of an ordinal less than  , or an iterated base   representation all of whose pieces are canonical, for some   where   is itself written in iterated base   representation all of whose pieces are canonical and less than  . The order is checked by lexicographic verification at all levels (keeping in mind that   is greater than any expression obtained by  , and for canonical values the greater   always trumps the lesser or even arbitrary sums, products and exponentials of the lesser).

For example,   is a canonical notation for an ordinal which is less than the Feferman-Schütte ordinal: it can be written using the Veblen functions as  .

Concerning the order, one might point out that   (the Feferman-Schütte ordinal) is much more than   (because   is greater than   of anything), and   is itself much more than   (because   is greater than  , so any sum-product-or-exponential expression involving   and smaller value will remain less than  ). In fact,   is already less than  .

Standard sequences for ordinal notations edit

To witness the fact that we have defined notations for ordinals below the Bachmann-Howard ordinal (which are all of countable cofinality), we might define standard sequences converging to any one of them (provided it is a limit ordinal, of course). Actually we will define canonical sequences for certain uncountable ordinals, too, namely the uncountable ordinals of countable cofinality (if we are to hope to define a sequence converging to them…) which are representable (that is, all of whose  -pieces are less than the Bachmann-Howard ordinal).

The following rules are more or less obvious, except for the last:

  • First, get rid of the (iterated) base   representations: to define a standard sequence converging to  , where   is either   or   (or  , but see below):
    • if   is zero then   and there is nothing to be done;
    • if   is zero and   is successor, then   is successor and there is nothing to be done;
    • if   is limit, take the standard sequence converging to   and replace   in the expression by the elements of that sequence;
    • if   is successor and   is limit, rewrite the last term   as   and replace the exponent   in the last term by the elements of the fundamental sequence converging to it;
    • if   is successor and   is also, rewrite the last term   as   and replace the last   in this expression by the elements of the fundamental sequence converging to it.
  • If   is  , then take the obvious  ,  ,  ,  … as the fundamental sequence for  .
  • If   then take as fundamental sequence for   the sequence  ,  ,  
  • If   then take as fundamental sequence for   the sequence  ,  ,  
  • If   where   is a limit ordinal of countable cofinality, define the standard sequence for   to be obtained by applying   to the standard sequence for   (recall that   is continuous, here).
  • It remains to handle the case where   with   an ordinal of uncountable cofinality (e.g.,   itself). Obviously it doesn't make sense to define a sequence converging to   in this case; however, what we can define is a sequence converging to some   with countable cofinality and such that   is constant between   and  . This   will be the first fixed point of a certain (continuous and non-decreasing) function  . To find it, apply the same rules (from the base   representation of  ) as to find the canonical sequence of  , except that whenever a sequence converging to   is called for (something which cannot exist), replace the   in question, in the expression of  , by a   (where   is a variable) and perform a repeated iteration (starting from  , say) of the function  : this gives a sequence  ,  ,  … tending to  , and the canonical sequence for   is  ,  ,  … (The examples below should make this clearer.)

Here are some examples for the last (and most interesting) case:

  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  … This indeed converges to   after which   is constant until  .
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  … This indeed converges to the value of   at   after which   is constant until  .
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  … This converges to the value of   at  .
  • The canonical sequence for   is  ,  ,  … This converges to the value of   at  .
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  … This converges to the value of   at  .
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  … This converges to the value of   at  .
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  … This converges to the value of   at  .
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  

Here are some examples of the other cases:

  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  ,  
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  ,  
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  ,  
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  ,  
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  ,  
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  ,  
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  … (this is derived from the fundamental sequence for  ).
  • The canonical sequence for   is:  ,  ,  … (this is derived from the fundamental sequence for  , which was given above).

Even though the Bachmann-Howard ordinal   itself has no canonical notation, it is also useful to define a canonical sequence for it: this is  ,  ,  

A terminating process edit

Start with any ordinal less or equal to the Bachmann-Howard ordinal, and repeat the following process so long as it is not zero:

  • if the ordinal is a successor, subtract one (that is, replace it with its predecessor),
  • if it is a limit, replace it by some element of the canonical sequence defined for it.

Then it is true that this process always terminates (as any decreasing sequence of ordinals is finite); however, like (but even more so than for) the hydra game:

  1. it can take a very long time to terminate,
  2. the proof of termination may be out of reach of certain weak systems of arithmetic.

To give some flavor of what the process feels like, here are some steps of it: starting from   (the small Veblen ordinal), we might go down to  , from there down to  , then   then   then   then   then   then   and so on. It appears as though the expressions are getting more and more complicated whereas, in fact, the ordinals always decrease.

Concerning the first statement, one could introduce, for any ordinal   less or equal to the Bachmann-Howard ordinal  , the integer function   which counts the number of steps of the process before termination if one always selects the  'th element from the canonical sequence. Then   can be a very fast growing function: already   is essentially  , the function   is comparable with the Ackermann function  , and   is quite unimaginable.

Concerning the second statement, a precise version is given by ordinal analysis: for example, Kripke-Platek set theory can prove that the process terminates for any given   less than the Bachmann-Howard ordinal, but it cannot do this uniformly, i.e., it cannot prove the termination starting from the Bachmann-Howard ordinal. Some theories like Peano arithmetic are limited by much smaller ordinals (  in the case of Peano arithmetic).

Variations on edit

Making the function less powerful edit

It is instructive (although not exactly useful) to make   less powerful.

If we alter the definition of   to omit exponentition from the repertoire from which   is constructed, then we get   (as this is the smallest ordinal which cannot be constructed from  ,   and   using addition and multiplication only), then   and similarly  ,   until we come to a fixed point which is then our  . We then have   and so on until  . Since multiplication of  's is permitted, we can still form   and   and so on, but our construction ends there as there is no way to get at or beyond  : so the range of this weakened system of notation is   (the value of   is the same in our weaker system as in our original system, except that now we cannot go beyond it). This does not even go as far as the Feferman-Schütte ordinal.

If we alter the definition of   yet some more to allow only addition as a primitive for construction, we get   and   and so on until   and still  . This time,   and so on until   and similarly  . But this time we can go no further: since we can only add  's, the range of our system is  .

In both cases, we find that the limitation on the weakened   function comes not so much from the operations allowed on the countable ordinals as on the uncountable ordinals we allow ourselves to denote.

Going beyond the Bachmann-Howard ordinal edit

We know that   is the Bachmann-Howard ordinal. The reason why   is no larger, with our definitions, is that there is no notation for   (it does not belong to   for any  , it is always the least upper bound of it). One could try to add the   function (or the Veblen functions of so-many-variables) to the allowed primitives beyond addition, multiplication and exponentiation, but that does not get us very far. To create more systematic notations for countable ordinals, we need more systematic notations for uncountable ordinals: we cannot use the   function itself because it only yields countable ordinals (e.g.,   is,  , certainly not  ), so the idea is to mimic its definition as follows:

Let   be the smallest ordinal which cannot be expressed from all countable ordinals,   and   using sums, products, exponentials, and the   function itself (to previously constructed ordinals less than  ).

Here,   is a new ordinal guaranteed to be greater than all the ordinals which will be constructed using  : again, letting   and   works.

For example,  , and more generally   for all countable ordinals and even beyond (  and  ): this holds up to the first fixed point   beyond   of the   function, which is the limit of  ,   and so forth. Beyond this, we have   and this remains true until  : exactly as was the case for  , we have   and  .

The   function gives us a system of notations (assuming we can somehow write down all countable ordinals!) for the uncountable ordinals below  , which is the limit of  ,   and so forth.

Now we can reinject these notations in the original   function, modified as follows:

  is the smallest ordinal which cannot be expressed from  ,  ,  ,   and   using sums, products, exponentials, the   function, and the   function itself (to previously constructed ordinals less than  ).

This modified function   coincides with the previous one up to (and including)   — which is the Bachmann-Howard ordinal. But now we can get beyond this, and   is   (the next  -number after the Bachmann-Howard ordinal). We have made our system doubly impredicative: to create notations for countable ordinals we use notations for certain ordinals between   and   which are themselves defined using certain ordinals beyond  .

An variation on this scheme, which makes little difference when using just two (or finitely many) collapsing functions, but becomes important for infinitely many of them, is to define

  is the smallest ordinal which cannot be expressed from  ,  ,  ,   and   using sums, products, exponentials, and the   and   function (to previously constructed ordinals less than  ).

i.e., allow the use of   only for arguments less than   itself. With this definition, we must write   instead of   (although it is still also equal to  , of course, but it is now constant until  ). This change is inessential because, intuitively speaking, the   function collapses the nameable ordinals beyond   below the latter so it matters little whether   is invoked directly on the ordinals beyond   or on their image by  . But it makes it possible to define   and   by simultaneous (rather than “downward”) induction, and this is important if we are to use infinitely many collapsing functions.

Indeed, there is no reason to stop at two levels: using   new cardinals in this way,  , we get a system essentially equivalent to that introduced by Buchholz[1], the inessential difference being that since Buchholz uses   ordinals from the start, he does not need to allow multiplication or exponentiation; also, Buchholz does not introduce the numbers   or   in the system as they will also be produced by the   functions: this makes the entire scheme much more elegant and more concise to define, albeit more difficult to understand. This system is also sensibly equivalent to the earlier (and much more difficult to grasp) “ordinal diagrams” of Takeuti and   functions of Feferman: their range is the same ( , which could be called the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal).

  1. ^ Buchholz, Wilfried (1986). "A New System of Proof-Theoretic Ordinal Notations". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 32: 195–207.