In mathematics, in particular the subfield of algebraic geometry, a rational map or rational mapping is a kind of partial function between algebraic varieties. This article uses the convention that varieties are irreducible.

Definition edit

Formal definition edit

Formally, a rational map   between two varieties is an equivalence class of pairs   in which   is a morphism of varieties from a non-empty open set   to  , and two such pairs   and   are considered equivalent if   and   coincide on the intersection   (this is, in particular, vacuously true if the intersection is empty, but since   is assumed irreducible, this is impossible). The proof that this defines an equivalence relation relies on the following lemma:

  • If two morphisms of varieties are equal on some non-empty open set, then they are equal.

  is said to be birational if there exists a rational map   which is its inverse, where the composition is taken in the above sense.

The importance of rational maps to algebraic geometry is in the connection between such maps and maps between the function fields of   and  . Even a cursory examination of the definitions reveals a similarity between that of rational map and that of rational function; in fact, a rational function is just a rational map whose range is the projective line. Composition of functions then allows us to "pull back" rational functions along a rational map, so that a single rational map   induces a homomorphism of fields  . In particular, the following theorem is central: the functor from the category of projective varieties with dominant rational maps (over a fixed base field, for example  ) to the category of finitely generated field extensions of the base field with reverse inclusion of extensions as morphisms, which associates each variety to its function field and each map to the associated map of function fields, is an equivalence of categories.

Examples edit

Rational maps of projective spaces edit

There is a rational map   sending a ratio  . Since the point   cannot have an image, this map is only rational, and not a morphism of varieties. More generally, there are rational maps   sending for   sending an  -tuple to an  -tuple by forgetting the last coordinates.

Inclusions of open subvarieties edit

On a connected variety  , the inclusion of any open subvariety   is a birational equivalence since the two varieties have equivalent function fields. That is, every rational function  can be restricted to a rational function   and conversely, a rational function   defines a rational equivalence class   on  . An excellent example of this phenomenon is the birational equivalence of   and  , hence  .

Covering spaces on open subsets edit

Covering spaces on open subsets of a variety give ample examples of rational maps which are not birational. For example, Belyi's theorem states that every algebraic curve   admits a map   which ramifies at three points. Then, there is an associated covering space   which defines a dominant rational morphism which is not birational. Another class of examples come from Hyperelliptic curves which are double covers of   ramified at a finite number of points. Another class of examples are given by a taking a hypersurface   and restricting a rational map   to  . This gives a ramified cover. For example, the Cubic surface given by the vanishing locus   has a rational map to   sending  . This rational map can be expressed as the degree   field extension

 

Resolution of singularities edit

One of the canonical examples of a birational map is the Resolution of singularities. Over a field of characteristic 0, every singular variety   has an associated nonsingular variety   with a birational map  . This map has the property that it is an isomorphism on   and the fiber over   is a normal crossing divisor. For example, a nodal curve such as   is birational to   since topologically it is an elliptic curve with one of the circles contracted. Then, the birational map is given by normalization.

Birational equivalence edit

Two varieties are said to be birationally equivalent if there exists a birational map between them; this theorem states that birational equivalence of varieties is identical to isomorphism of their function fields as extensions of the base field. This is somewhat more liberal than the notion of isomorphism of varieties (which requires a globally defined morphism to witness the isomorphism, not merely a rational map), in that there exist varieties which are birational but not isomorphic.

The usual example is that   is birational to the variety   contained in   consisting of the set of projective points   such that  , but not isomorphic. Indeed, any two lines in   intersect, but the lines in   defined by   and   cannot intersect since their intersection would have all coordinates zero. To compute the function field of   we pass to an affine subset (which does not change the field, a manifestation of the fact that a rational map depends only on its behavior in any open subset of its domain) in which  ; in projective space this means we may take   and therefore identify this subset with the affine  -plane. There, the coordinate ring of   is

 

via the map  . And the field of fractions of the latter is just  , isomorphic to that of  . Note that at no time did we actually produce a rational map, though tracing through the proof of the theorem it is possible to do so.

See also edit

References edit

  • Hartshorne, Robin (1977), Algebraic Geometry, Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag, ISBN 978-0-387-90244-9, MR 0463157, section I.4.