General Concept Lattice

The General Concept Lattice (GCL) proposes a novel general construction of concept hierarchy from formal context, where the conventional Formal Concept Lattice based on Formal Concept Analysis (FCA) only serves as a substructure.[1]

Table 1
Fig. 1: Three different formal concept lattices (FCLs) obtained from the three formal contexts describing the same 3BS, where balls are equipped with three distinct colours.

The formal context is a data table of heterogeneous relations illustrating how objects carrying attributes. By analogy with truth-value table, every formal context can develop its fully extended version including all the columns corresponding to attributes constructed, by means of Boolean operations, out of the given attribute set. The GCL is based on the extended formal context which comprehends the full information content of the formal context in the sense that it incorporates whatever the formal context should consistently imply. Noteworthily, different formal contexts may give rise to the same extended formal context.[2][3]

Background edit

The GCL[4] claims to take into account the extended formal context for the preservation of information content as follows. Consider describing a three-ball system (3BS) with three distinct colours ( red,  green,  blue). According to Table 1, one may refer to different attribute sets, say,  ,   or   to reach different formal contexts. The concept hierarchy for the 3BS is supposed to be unique regardless of how the 3BS being described. However, the FCA exhibits different formal concept lattices subject to the chosen formal contexts, see Fig. 1. In contrast, the GCL lattice structure remains invariant with respect to the different formal contexts chosen for the 3BS since they can infer each other and ultimately entail the same information content.

Table 1: The extended version for the formal context describing the 3BS. From   one can also deduce  , thereby deducing the full  . Note that  , ,  .
     
 
 
                     
1        
2          
3        

In information science, the Formal Concept Analysis (FCA) promises practical applications in various fields owing to the following fundamental characteristics.

  • It orders the formal concepts in a hierarchy i.e. the formal concept lattice (FCL) which can be graphically visualized as a line diagram that may be helpful for understanding the data.
  • It enables the attribute exploration,[5] a knowledge acquisition technique based on implications. It is possible to acquire the canonical (Guigues-Duquenne[6]) basis, the non-redundant collection of informative implications based on which valid implications available from the formal context can be derived by the Armstrong rules.

The FCL does not appear to be the only lattice applicable to the interpretation of data table. Alternative concept lattices subject to different derivation operators based on the notions relevant to the Rough Set Analysis have also been proposed.[7][8][9] Specifically, the object-oriented concept lattice,[9] which is  referred to as the rough set lattice[4] (RSL) afterwards, is found to be particularly instructive to supplement the standard FCA in further understandings of the formal context.

  • The FCL exhibits the categorisation for object class according to their common properties while the RSL is according to those properties which other classes do not possess.
  • The RSL provides an alternative scheme for implications available from the formal context which are beyond the scope of FCL, as will be clarified later. 

Consequently, there are two crucial points to be contemplated.

 
Fig. 2: Three different rough set lattices, cf. Fig. 1, obtained from the same three formal contexts describing the 3BS.
  • The FCL and RSL reflect different concept hierarchies interpreting the same formal context in a complementary way. However, similar to the case of FCL, RSL also suffers from different lattice structures varying with respect to the chosen formal contexts, see Fig. 2.
  • The implication relations extracted via the RSL from the formal context signify a different part of logic content from the ones extractable via the FCL. The treatment via the RSL would require further efforts of construction, the Guigues-Duquenne basis for the RSL. Moreover, it is unwarranted that the implications of these two together suffices the full logic content.

The GCL accomplishes a sound theoretical foundation for the concept hierarchies acquired from formal context.[4] Maintaining the generality that preserves the information, the GCL underlies both the FCL and RSL, which correspond to substructures at particular restrictions. Technically, the GCL would be reduced to the FCL and RSL when restricted to conjunctions and disjunctions of elements in the referred attribute set ( ), respectively. In addition, the GCL unveils extra information complementary to the results via the FCL and RSL. Surprisingly, the implementation of formal context via GCL is much more manageable than those via FCL and RSL.

Related mathematical formulations edit

Algebras of derivation operators edit

The derivation operators constitute the building blocks of concept lattices and thus deserve distinctive notations. Subject to a formal context concerning the object set   and attribute set  ,

 
 
 

are considered as different modal operators[7][8] (Sufficiency, Necessity and Possibility, respectively) that generalise the FCA. For notations,  , the operator adopted in the standard FCA,[1][2][3] follows Bernhard Ganter [de][10] and R. Wille;[1]   as well as   follows Y. Y. Yao.[9] By  , i.e.,   the object   carries the attribute   as its property, which is also referred to as   where   is the set of all objects carrying the attribute  .

With   it is straightforward to check that

   

where the same relations hold if given in terms of  .

Two Galois lattices edit

Galois connections edit

From the above algebras, there exist different types of Galois connections, e.g.,

(1)    , (2)    

and (3)     that corresponds to (2) when one replaces  and  . Note that (1) and (2) enable different object-oriented constructions for the concept hierarchies FCL and RSL, respectively. Note that (3) corresponds to the attribute-oriented construction[9] where the roles of object and attribute in the RSL are exchanged. The FCL and RSL apply to different 2-tuple   concept collections that manifest different well-defined partial orderings.

Two concept hierarchies edit

Given as a concept, the 2-tuple   is in general constituted by an extent   and an intent  , which should be distinguished when applied to FCL and RSL. The concept   is furnished by   based on (1) while   is furnished by   based on (2). In essence, there are two Galois lattices based on different orderings of the two collections of concepts as follows.

  entails   and  
since   iff  , and   iff  .
  entails   and  
since   iff  , and   iff  .

Common extents of FCL and RSL edit

Every attribute listed in the formal context provides an extent for FCL and RSL simultaneously via the object set carrying the attribute. Though the extents for FCL and for RSL do not coincide totally, every   for   is known to be a common extent of FCL and RSL. This turns up from the main results in FCL (Formale Begriffsanalyse#Hauptsatz der Formalen Begriffsanalyse [de]) and RSL: every   ( ) is an extent for FCL[1][2][3] and  is an extent for RSL.[9] Note that[4] choosing   gives rise to  .

Two types of informative implications edit

The consideration of the attribute set-to-set implication   ( ) via FCL has an intuitive interpretation:[6] every object possessing all the attributes in   possesses all the attributes in  , in other words  . Alternatively, one may consider   based on the RSL in a similar manner:[4] the set of all objects carrying any of the attributes in   is contained in the set of all objects carrying any of the attributes in  , in other words  . It is apparent that   and   relate different pairs of attribute sets and are incapable of expressing each other.

Extension of formal context edit

For every formal context one may acquire its extended version deduced in the sense of completing a truth-value table. It is instructive to explicitly label the object/attribute dependence for the formal context,[4] say,   rather than   since one may have to investigate more than one formal contexts. As is illustrated in Table 1,   can be employed to deduce the extended version  , where   is the set of all attributes constructed out of elements in   by means of Boolean operations. Note that   includes three columns reflecting the use of   and   the attribute set  .

Obtaining the general concept lattice edit

Observations based on mathematical facts edit

Intents in terms of single attributes edit

The FCL and RSL will not be altered if their intents are interpreted as single attributes.[4]

  can be understood as   with   (the conjunction of all elements in  ),  plays the role of   since  .
  can be understood as   with   (the disjunction of all elements in  ),  plays the role of   since  .

Here, the dot product   stands for the conjunction (the dots is often omitted for compactness) and the summation   the disjunction, which are notations in the Curry-Howard style. Note that the orderings become

  and  , both are implemented by    .

Implications from single attribute to single attribute edit

Concerning the implications extracted from formal context,

   serves as the general form of implication relations available from the formal context, which holds for any pair of   fulfilling  .

Note that   turns out to be trivial if  , which entails  . Intuitively,[4] every object carrying   is an object carrying  , which means the implication any object having the property   must also have the property  . In particular,

  can be interpreted as   with   and  ,
  can be interpreted as   with   and  ,

where   and   collapse into  .

Lattice of 3-tuple concepts with double Galois connection edit

When extended to  , the algebras of derivation operators remain formally unchanged, apart from the generalisation from   to   which is signified in terms of[4] the replacements  ,   and  . The concepts under consideration become then   and  , where   and  , which are constructions allowable by the two Galois connections  and  , respectively. Henceforth,

  and   for  ,   and   for  .

The extents for the two concepts now coincide exactly. All the attributes in   are listed in the formal context  , each contributes a common extent for FCL and RSL. Furthermore, the collection of these common extents   amounts to   which exhausts all the possible unions of the minimal object sets discernible by the formal context. Note that each   collects objects of the same property, see Table 2. One may then join   and   into a 3-tuple with common extent:

   where  ,   and  .

Note that  are introduced in order to differentiate the two intents. Clearly, the number of these 3-tuples equals the cardinality of set of common extent which counts  . Moreover,   manifests well-defined ordering. For  , where  and  ,

  iff   and   and  .

Emergence of the GCL edit

While it is generically impossible to determine   subject to  , the structure of concept hierarchy need not rely on these intents directly. An efficient way[4] to implement the concept hierarchy for   is to consider intents in terms of single attributes. Let henceforth   and  . Upon introducing   it is straightforward to check that   and  ,  . Therefore,  , which is a closed interval bounded from below by   and from above by   since  . Moreover,

  iff  ,   iff   iff  .

In addition,   which means that the collection of intents   in fact exhausts all the generalised attributes  in comparison to  . Then, the GCL enters as the lattice structure   based on the formal context via  :

  • The collection of all the general concepts   constitutes the poset   ordered as
  iff   and   and  .
  • Both   (meet) and   (join) operations are applicable for finding further lattice points:
 , where  
 , where 
  • The GCL appears to be a complete lattice since both   and   can be found in  :
 ,  .

Consequence of the general concept lattice edit

Manageable general lattice edit

The construction for FCL was known to count on efficient algorithms,[11][12] not to mention the construction for RSL which did not receive much attention yet. Intriguingly, though the GCL furnishes the general structure on which both the FCL and RSL can be rediscovered, the GCL can be acquired via simple readout.

Reading out the lattice edit

The completion of GCL[4] is equivalent to the completion of the intents of GCL in terms of the lower and bounds.

  • The lower bounds   can be employed to determine the upper bounds  , and vice versa. For concreteness, both   and   are extents of the GCL,   coexists with   . Subsequently,   and  , where  .
  • The lower bounds of intents corresponding to minimal discernible object sets ( s for  ) can be employed to determine all the intents. Note that   and   appears to be a direct readout by means of  .
 
Fig. 3: Identifying FCL and RSL on the GCL for the 3BS according to the formal context   in Table 1. Every general intent   comprises all the attributes uniquely possessed by the object set   in common. Elements on   can be ordered as a Hasse diagram identifiable with the closed interval   where  .

The above enables the determinations of the intents depicted as in Fig. 3 for the 3BS given by Table 1, where one can read out that  ,   and  . Hence, e.g.,  ,  . Note that the GCL also appears to be a Hasse diagram due to the resemblance of its extents to a power set. Moreover, each intent   at   also exhibits another Hasse diagram isomorphic to the ordering of attributes in the closed interval  . It can be shown that   where   with  . Hence,   making the cardinality   a constant given as  . Clearly, one may check that 

Rediscovering FCL and RSL on the GCL edit

The GCL underlies the original FCL and RSL subject to  , as one can tell from   and  . To rediscover a node for FCL, one looks for a conjunction of attributes in   contained in  , which can be identified within the conjunctive normal form of   if exists. Likewise, for the RSL one looks for a disjunction of attributes in   contained in  , which can be found within the disjunctive normal form of  , see Fig 3. For instance, from the node   on the GCL,     . It happens that both the FCL and RSL have the concept   in common. Note that   appears to be the only attribute belonging to  , which is simultaneously a conjunction and a disjunction. To illustrate a different situation,    . Apparently,   is the attribute emerging as disjunction of elements in   which belongs to  , in which no attribute composed by conjunction of elements in   is found. Hence,   could not be an extent of FCL, it only constitutes the concept   for the RSL.

Information content of a formal context edit

Informative implications as equivalence due to categorisation edit

Non-tautological implication relations signify the information contained in the formal context and are referred to as informative implications.[6] In general,   entails the implication  . The implication is informative if it is   (i.e.  ).

In case it is strictly  , one has   where  . Then,   can be replaced by means of   together with the tautology  . Therefore, what remains to be taken into account is the equivalence   for some  . Logically, both attributes are properties carried by the same object class,   reflects that equivalence relation.

All attributes in   must be mutually implied,[4] which can be implemented, e.g., by   (in fact,   where   is a tautology), i.e., all attributes are equivalent to the lower bound of intent.

A formula that implements all the informative implications edit

Extraction of the implications of type   from the formal context was known to be complicated,[13][14][15][16][17] it necessitates efforts for constructing a canonical basis, which does not apply to the implications of type  . By contrast, the above equivalence only proposes[4]

  • the single formula generating all the informative implications:
 , which can be restated as  ,
  • as an auxiliary formula,
  is allowed by the formal context iff   (or  ).

Hence, purely algebraic formulae can be employed to determine the implication relations, one need not consult the object-attribute dependence in the formal context, which is the typical effort in finding the canonical basis.

Remarkably,   and   are referred to as the contextual truth and falsity, respectively.     and   as well as   and   similar to the conventional truth 1 and falsity 0 that can be identified with   and  , respectively.

Beyond the set-to-set implications edit

  and   are found to be particular forms of  . Assume   and   for both cases. By  , an object set carrying all the attributes in   implies carrying all the attributes in   simultaneously, i.e.  . By  , an object set carrying any of the attributes in   implies carrying some of the attributes in  , therefore  . Notably, the point of view conjunction-to-conjunction has been adopted by Ganter[5] while dealing with the attribute exploration.

One could overlook significant parts of the logic content in formal context were it not for the consideration based on the GCL. Here, the formal context describing 3BS given in Table 1 suggests an extreme case where no implication of the type   could be found. Nevertheless, one ends up, e.g.,   (or  ), whose meaning appears to be ambiguous. Though it is true that  , one also notices that   as well as    . Indeed, by using the above formula with the   provided in Fig. 2 it can be seen that    , hence it is   and   that underlies  .

Remarkably, the same formula will lead to (1)   (or  ) and (2)   (or  ), where  ,   and   can be interchanged. Hence, what one has captured from the 3BS are that (1) no two colours could coexist and that (2) there is no colour other than  ,   and  . The two issues are certainly less trivial in the scopes of   and  .

Rules to assemble or transform implications edit

The rules to assemble or transform implications of type   are of direct consequences of object set inclusion relations. Notably, some of these rules can be reduced to the Armstrong axioms, which pertain to the main considerations of Guigues and Duquenne[6] based on the non-redundant collection of informative implications acquired via FCL. In particular,

(1)   and      
since   and   leads to  , i.e.,  .

In the case of  ,  ,   and  , where   are sets of attributes, the rule (1) can be re-expressed as Armstrong's composition:

(1')   and     
  and  .

The Armstrong axioms are not suited for   which requires  . This is in contrast to   for which Armstrong's reflexivity is implemented by  . Nevertheless, a similar composition may occur but signify a different rule from (1). Note that one also arrives at

(2)   and      
since   and      , which gives rise to
(2')   and      whenever  ,  ,   and  .

Example edit

For concreteness, consider the example depicted by Table 2, which has been originally adopted for clarification of the RSL[9] but worked out for the GCL.[4]

Table 2: An example formal context. Since the objects   are equipped with the same property, they belong to the same minimal discernible object set. One may choose  ,  ,  ,   and  . Note that the fully extended version   comprises  columns, where the cardinality of attribute set  . The table is huge, yet manageable when one deals with the GCL.
   
 
 
                     
1            
2        
3        
4        
5      
6          

The GCL structure and the identifications of FCL and RSL on the GCL edit

  • The determinations of the nodes of GCL for Table 2 are straightforward, as is depicted in Fig.4. For example, one may read out
     
    Fig. 4: Readout of GCL from a formal context. On each node, a binary string is to denote the extent, e.g., 01010 denotes the object set   i.e.  , 00100 denotes   i.e.  . In this figure,   and   are shown. Accordingly, one may identify all the lower and upper bounds of intents in the expressions the contextual truth and falsity (  and  ), respectively.
       ,
   ,
   , and so forth.

Clearly, one may also check that  .

  • To rediscover the original FCL and RSL see Fig. 5. Observe, e.g.,
             ,
       .

Within the expression of   it can be seen that   , while within   it can be seen    . Therefore, one finds out the concepts   for FCL and   for RSL. By contrast,

   ,    

with     gives rise to the concept   for FCL however fails to provide an extent for RSL because  .

 
Fig. 5: The GCL constructed according to the formal context given in Table 2. The circled points are nodes existing on the FCL, whereas the bold ones belong to the RSL, also cf. Fig. 3.

Implication relations in general edit

  • The meanings of   and   are essentially different.
  and   denote   and  , respectively.

For the present case, the above relations can be examined via the auxiliary formula:

  (or  ),   (or  ).
  •   and   are equivalent when both   are reduced to sets of single element.
Both   and  , according to the formal context of Table 2, are interpreted as  , which means   based on  and   based on  .

Note that        . Moreover,   entails both   and  , which correspond to   and  , respectively.

  • The single formula suffices to generate all the informative implications, where one may choose any attribute in   as the antecedent or consequent.
(1) With   one may infer the properties of objects of interest from the condition   by specifying  , thereby incorporating abundant informative implications as equivalent relations between any pair of attributes within the interval  , i.e.,     if   and  . Note that   entails   since  .

For instance, by       the relation     is neither of the type   nor of the type  . Nevertheless, one may also derive, e.g.,  ,   and  , which are  ,   and  , respectively. As a further interesting implication   entails   by means of material implication. Namely, for the objects carrying the property   or  ,   must hold and, in addition, objects carrying the property   must also carry the property   and vice versa.

(1') Alternatively, the equivalent formula   can be employed to specify the objects of particular interest. In effect,     if   and  .

One may be interested in the properties inferring a particular consequent, say,  . Consider     giving rise to     according to Table 2. Clearly, with      one has  . This gives rise to many possible antecedents such as  ,  ,  ,   and so forth.

(2)   governs all the implications extractable from the formal context by means of (1) and (1'). Indeed, it plays the role of canonical basis with one single implication relation.

  can be understood as   or equivalently  , which turns out be the only non-redundant implication one needs to deduce all the informative implications from any formal context. The basis   or   suffices the deduction of all implications as follows. While      and     , choosing either   or   gives rise to  . Notably, this encompasses (1) and (1') by means of      for any  , where   can be identified with some   corresponding to one of the 32 nodes on the GCL in Fig. 4.

  develops equivalence, at each single node, for all attributes contained within the interval  . Moreover, informative implications could also relate different nodes via Hypothetical syllogism by invoking tautology. Typically,     whenever    . This corresponds to the cases considered in (1'):  ,  ,   etc. Explicitly,   is based upon   and   where  . Note that    and    while    (also  ). Therefore,  . Similarly,   with   gives  .

Indeed,   or equivalently   plays the role of canonical basis with one single implication relation.

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d Wille, Rudolf (2005), "Formal Concept Analysis as Mathematical Theory of Concepts and Concept Hierarchies", Formal Concept Analysis, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 3626, Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg, pp. 1–33, doi:10.1007/11528784_1, ISBN 978-3-540-27891-7, S2CID 14153929, archived from the original on 2024-02-25, retrieved 2023-07-16
  2. ^ a b c Wille, Rudolf (1982), "Restructuring Lattice Theory: An Approach Based on Hierarchies of Concepts", Ordered Sets, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 445–470, doi:10.1007/978-94-009-7798-3_15, ISBN 978-94-009-7800-3, archived from the original on 2024-02-25, retrieved 2023-07-16
  3. ^ a b c Ganter, Bernhard; Wille, Rudolf (1999). Formal Concept Analysis. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-59830-2. ISBN 978-3-540-62771-5. S2CID 262487114. Archived from the original on 2024-02-25. Retrieved 2023-07-16.
  4. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Liaw, Tsong-Ming; Lin, Simon C. (2020-10-12). "A general theory of concept lattice with tractable implication exploration". Theoretical Computer Science. 837: 84–114. doi:10.1016/j.tcs.2020.05.014. ISSN 0304-3975. S2CID 219514253. Archived from the original on 2020-05-28. Retrieved 2023-07-19.
  5. ^ a b Ganter, Bernhard; Obiedkov, Sergei (2016). Conceptual exploration. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-3-662-49290-1.
  6. ^ a b c d Guigues, J. L.; Duquenne, V. (1986). "Familles minimales d'implications informatives résultant d'un tableau de données binaires". Mathématiques et Sciences Humaines. 95: 5–18. ISSN 0987-6936. Archived from the original on 2022-04-19. Retrieved 2023-07-19.
  7. ^ a b Duntsch, N.; Gediga, G. (2002). "Modal-style operators in qualitative data analysis". 2002 IEEE International Conference on Data Mining, 2002. Proceedings. IEEE Comput. Soc. pp. 155–162. doi:10.1109/ICDM.2002.1183898. ISBN 978-0-7695-1754-4. S2CID 13170017. Archived from the original on 2023-12-06. Retrieved 2024-01-07.
  8. ^ a b Düntsch, Ivo; Gediga, Günther (2003), "Approximation Operators in Qualitative Data Analysis", Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg, pp. 214–230, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-24615-2_10, ISBN 978-3-540-20780-1, archived from the original on 2024-02-25, retrieved 2023-07-19
  9. ^ a b c d e f Yao, Y.Y. (2004). "Concept lattices in rough set theory". IEEE Annual Meeting of the Fuzzy Information, 2004. Processing NAFIPS '04. IEEE. pp. 796-801 Vol.2. doi:10.1109/nafips.2004.1337404. ISBN 0-7803-8376-1. S2CID 6716057. Archived from the original on 2024-02-25. Retrieved 2023-07-19.
  10. ^ Ganter, Bernhard (1999-04-06). "Attribute exploration with background knowledge". Theoretical Computer Science. ORDAL'96. 217 (2): 215–233. doi:10.1016/S0304-3975(98)00271-0. ISSN 0304-3975. Archived from the original on 2023-08-17. Retrieved 2023-08-17.
  11. ^ Kuznetsov, Sergei O. (2001-12-01). "On Computing the Size of a Lattice and Related Decision Problems". Order. 18 (4): 313–321. doi:10.1023/A:1013970520933. ISSN 1572-9273. S2CID 11571279. Archived from the original on 2024-02-25. Retrieved 2023-08-12.
  12. ^ Kuznetsov, Sergei O.; Obiedkov, Sergei A. (April 2002). "Comparing performance of algorithms for generating concept lattices". Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence. 14 (2–3): 189–216. doi:10.1080/09528130210164170. ISSN 0952-813X. S2CID 10784843. Archived from the original on 2023-10-17. Retrieved 2023-08-12.
  13. ^ Kuznetsov, Sergei O.; Obiedkov, Sergei (2008-06-06). "Some decision and counting problems of the Duquenne–Guigues basis of implications". Discrete Applied Mathematics. In Memory of Leonid Khachiyan (1952–2005 ). 156 (11): 1994–2003. doi:10.1016/j.dam.2007.04.014. ISSN 0166-218X. Archived from the original on 2023-09-04. Retrieved 2023-09-04.
  14. ^ Sertkaya, Barış (2009). "Towards the Complexity of Recognizing Pseudo-intents". In Rudolph, Sebastian; Dau, Frithjof; Kuznetsov, Sergei O. (eds.). Archived copy. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 5662. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer. pp. 284–292. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-03079-6_22. ISBN 978-3-642-03079-6. Archived from the original on 2023-09-04. Retrieved 2023-09-04. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link)
  15. ^ Distel, Felix (2010). "Hardness of Enumerating Pseudo-intents in the Lectic Order". In Kwuida, Léonard; Sertkaya, Barış (eds.). Archived copy. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 5986. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer. pp. 124–137. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-11928-6_9. ISBN 978-3-642-11928-6. Archived from the original on 2023-09-04. Retrieved 2023-09-04. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link)
  16. ^ Distel, Felix; Sertkaya, Barış (2011-03-28). "On the complexity of enumerating pseudo-intents". Discrete Applied Mathematics. 159 (6): 450–466. doi:10.1016/j.dam.2010.12.004. ISSN 0166-218X. S2CID 17769297. Archived from the original on 2023-09-04. Retrieved 2023-09-04.
  17. ^ Babin, Mikhail A.; Kuznetsov, Sergei O. (2013-04-01). "Computing premises of a minimal cover of functional dependencies is intractable". Discrete Applied Mathematics. 161 (6): 742–749. doi:10.1016/j.dam.2012.10.026. ISSN 0166-218X. Archived from the original on 2023-09-04. Retrieved 2023-09-04.