Feferman–Vaught theorem

Feferman–Vaught theorem[1] in model theory is a theorem by Solomon Feferman and Robert Lawson Vaught that shows how to reduce, in an algorithmic way, the first-order theory of a product of structures to the first-order theory of elements of the structure.

The theorem is considered as one of the standard results in model theory.[2][3][4] The theorem extends the previous result of Andrzej Mostowski on direct products of theories.[5] It generalizes (to formulas with arbitrary quantifiers) the property in universal algebra that equalities (identities) carry over to direct products of algebraic structures (which is a consequence of one direction of Birkhoff's theorem).

Direct product of structures edit

Consider a first-order logic signature L. The definition of product structures takes a family of L-structures   for   for some index set I and defines the product structure  , which is also an L-structure, with all functions and relations defined pointwise.

The definition generalizes the direct product in universal algebra to structures for languages that contain not only function symbols but also relation symbols.

If   is a relation symbol with   arguments in L and   are elements of the cartesian product, we define the interpretation of   in   by

 

When   is a functional relation, this definition reduces to the definition of direct product in universal algebra.

Statement of the theorem for direct products edit

For a first-order formula   in signature L with free variables, and for an interpretation   of the variables  , we define the set of indices   for which   holds in  

 

Given a first-order formula with free variables  , there is an algorithm to compute its equivalent game normal form, which is a finite disjunction   of mutually contradictory formulas.

The Feferman–Vaught theorem gives an algorithm that takes a first-order formula   and constructs a formula   that reduces the condition that   holds in the product to the condition that   holds in the interpretation of   sets of indices:

 

Formula   is thus a formula with   free set variables, for example, in the first-order theory of Boolean algebra of sets.

Proof idea edit

Formula   can be constructed following the structure of the starting formula  . When   is quantifier free then, by definition of direct product above it follows

 

Consequently, we can take   to be the equality   in the language of boolean algebra of sets (equivalently, the field of sets).

Extending the condition to quantified formulas can be viewed as a form of quantifier elimination, where quantification over product elements   in   is reduced to quantification over subsets of  .

Generalized products edit

It is often of interest to consider substructure of the direct product structure. If the restriction that defines product elements that belong to the substructure can be expressed as a condition on the sets of index elements, then the results can be generalized.

An example is the substructure of product elements that are constant at all but finitely many indices. Assume that the language L contains a constant symbol   and consider the substructure containing only those product elements   for which the set

 

is finite. The theorem then reduces the truth value in such substructure to a formula   in the boolean algebra of sets, where certain sets are restricted to be finite.

One way to define generalized products is to consider those substructures where the sets   belong to some boolean algebra   of sets   of indices (a subset of the powerset set algebra  ), and where the product substructure admits gluing.[6] Here admitting gluing refers to the following closure condition: if   are two product elements and   is the element of the boolean algebra, then so is the element   defined by "gluing"   and   according to  :

 

Consequences edit

Feferman–Vaught theorem implies the decidability of Skolem arithmetic by viewing, via the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, the structure of natural numbers with multiplication as a generalized product (power) of Presburger arithmetic structures.

Given an ultrafilter on the set of indices  , we can define a quotient structure on product elements, leading to the theorem of Jerzy Łoś that can be used to construct hyperreal numbers.

References edit

  1. ^ Feferman, S; Vaught, R (1959). "The first order properties of products of algebraic systems". Fundamenta Mathematicae. 47 (1): 57–103.
  2. ^ Hodges, Wilfrid (1993). "Section 9.6: Feferman-Vaught theorem". Model theory. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521304423.
  3. ^ Karp, Carol (August 1967). "S. Feferman and R. L. Vaught. The first order properties of products of algebraic systems. Fundamenta mathematicae, vol, 47 (1959), pp. 57–103. (Review)". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 32 (2): 276–276. doi:10.2307/2271704.
  4. ^ Monk, J. Donald (1976). "23: Generalized Products". Mathematical Logic. Graduate Texts in Mathematics. Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-0-387-90170-1.
  5. ^ Mostowski, Andrzej (March 1952). "On direct products of theories". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 17 (1): 1–31. doi:10.2307/2267454.
  6. ^ Hodges, Wilfrid (1993). "Section 9.6: Feferman-Vaught theorem". Model theory. Cambridge University Press. p. 459. ISBN 0521304423.